Topic > The concept of the categorical imperative and Kant's moral philosophy in Immanuel Kant's Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals is a text that asks to be understood starting from some of the philosopher's best-known concepts, including the categorical imperative, which is introduced in the book as a way to evaluate the motivations for individual action. For Kant, a proposition declaring a certain action necessary includes ways of evaluating the motivations of one's actions. This is in contrast to the hypothetical imperatives that Kant suggests, outlining the means to ends: for example, if I want to feel full of energy, I must eat something with sugar. On the other hand, a categorical imperative conveys a universal. This is described in Kant's formulation of the categorical imperative as: “Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will it to become a universal law” (Kant, 1993, p. 30). He suggests that through “pure practical reason” we can ethically decide what is right and what is not. Importantly, Kant contrasts this with “pure reason,” which is the ability to know whether something is true without ever having proven it, and “practical reason” which allows us to understand the world we live in. Therefore, the ability to ethically decide what is law is based on pure practical reason outlined in the Foundations. Say no to plagiarism. Get a tailor-made essay on "Why Violent Video Games Shouldn't Be Banned"? Get an original essay For Kant, the ability to use practical reason has an important role to play in morality because it moves even without dependent incentives. For Kant, this means that human reasoning is based on the pure practical reasoning of choosing actions at the basic level because they are good, which Kant describes as the basis of the nature of good will. He argues that to be good and moral in and of itself requires acting with pure practical reason, which becomes part of a larger transcendental law that impacts how humans use reason pragmatically. Kant developed his moral philosophy after experiencing dissatisfaction with the moral philosophy of his time. He established that reason, different from how one experiences the world empirically, could also be used to examine moral events and circumstances. The concept of reason significantly prefigures Kant's work and becomes a fundamental principle of moral reason. For Kant, moral questions could be resolved by examining them with respect to pure practical reason, independently of any other empirical factors. As such, morality is not defined by the senses, but is achieved a priori, through pure practical reason. The principle determining whether or not moral questions can be examined, net of other sensible factors, is what makes morality, for Kant, universally applicable. As a result, moral universalism came to predominate in Kant's moral philosophy and became one of his most distinctive contributions to this field. As human beings, Kant believed that we all seek to exercise some measure of freedom and desire. However, for Kant, self-consciousness meant coming to terms with individual autonomy and the ability to exercise free will. According to Kant, "the faculty of desire according to concepts, insofar as the motive that determines it to action is found in itself and not in its object, is called the faculty of doing or abstaining from doing as one does." like” (Kant, 1993, p. 213). This means that those who use free will have an interesting feature: they allow us to empirically see an object in action and with desire, they are able to ground the will in the deterrent choice of action. Strictly speaking, the will has no basis in and of itselfself, but can be determined by what Kant calls “inclination” which fundamentally involves our human senses and the ability to see and judge situations empirically, which affects the autonomy of individual actions because this in effect refers to what it means to be “free,” or having free will, which Kant advocated, one must be able to understand it in relation to a causal power, but yet without causality to do so. In Kant's First Formulation on Universality and the Law of Nature there is an example of how Kant develops the moral proposition necessary for what he calls the “universalizing principle” (Kant, 1993, p. 92). For Kant, this is based on a formulation of the law of nature that can be reduced to what Kant calls “Act as if the maxims of your action were to become through your will a universal law of nature” (Kant, 1993, p. 421). . Consequently, Kant believed that, in granting any kind of moral responsibility and/or moral autonomy, a property must contain the will to be a law in and of itself. There is therefore a law of nature that has a universalizing force and that morality as such is fundamental to learning it. This allowed Kant to develop his idea of ​​the categorical imperative as universal. It follows that for Kant the construction of moral law is fundamentally based on the categorical imperative, which acts independently of individual interests or desires. Pure practical reason, outlined by Kant, is a way of evaluating an individual's motivations for action and as such determine what our imperative-based duties are. In short, an imperative is basically a command that governs our actions. For example, being told to pay taxes is an imperative, as is being told not to eat or kill animals. However, for Kant it is the categorical imperatives that command unconditional sublimation to what he calls the “universalizing principle” that links morality to categorical imperatives. He argues that for morality to function as such, it must be based on a universalizing command that cannot simply be ignored. This is how Kant's categorical imperative and pure practical reason come into play in morality. However, numerous philosophers over the years have attempted to debunk Kant's moral philosophy. Some critics have posited a thought experiment in response to Kant's moral philosophy, who argue that it can be seen in relation to the “Golden Rule” (quote). One of the major challenges to Kant's reasoning in the Groundwork came during his lifetime from a The French philosopher Benjamin Constant, believing Kant's categorical imperative to be flawed, offered a thought experiment that showed his inner incorrigibility. Constant said that according to Kant's categorical imperative, it would be impossible to lie to a known murderer, thus suggesting that there is a weakness and the crux of Kant's moral basis. Constant suggested that there was an inherent weakness in Kant's premises because if one could not lie to a murderer, moral actions did not always arise from pure practical reason. This challenge considered the possibility of moral actions as a means to an end, which Kant denied in his response to this challenge, stating that this in turn would deny being free and rational actors in the first place. The claim that lying to a murderer undermines Kant's premise of the categorical imperative is based on the simple assumption that all moral actions are not universal and that some may have unintentional means of achieving final goals. This is reminiscent of the school of classical realism and the morality of those like Machiavelli, who see the means to an end as the only possible way to develop a., 77(9), 515-572.